A&A 376, 17-27 (2001)
DOI: 10.1051/0004-6361:20010952
M. Lachièze-Rey
Service d'Astrophysique, CE Saclay, 91191 Gif-sur-Yvette Cedex, France
Received 16 May 2001 / Accepted 29 June 2001
Abstract
I provide a prescription to define space, at a given moment,
for an arbitrary observer in an arbitrary (sufficiently regular)
curved space-time. This prescription, based on synchronicity (simultaneity)
arguments, defines a foliation of space-time, which
corresponds to a family of canonically associated observers. It
provides also a natural global reference frame (with space and time coordinates)
for the observer, in space-time (or rather in the part of it which is causally
connected to him), which remains Minkowskian along his world-line. This
definition intends to provide a basis for the problem of
quantization in curved space-time, and/or for non inertial observers.
Application to Minkowski spacetime illustrates clearly the fact that different
observers see different spaces. For example, it allows one to define
space everywhere without ambiguity, for the Langevin observer
(involved in the Langevin pseudoparadox of twins).
Applied to the Rindler observer (with uniform acceleration) it leads
to the Rindler coordinates, whose choice is so justified with a
physical basis. This leads to an interpretation
of the Unruh effect, as due to the observer-dependence of the definition of
space (and time).
This prescription is also applied in cosmology, for inertial observers
in the Friedmann-Lemaître models: space for the observer appears to differ from
the hypersurfaces of homogeneity, which do not obey the simultaneity
requirement. I work out two examples: the Einstein-de Sitter model, in which
space, for an inertial observer, is not flat nor homogeneous, and the
de Sitter case.
Key words: cosmology: muscellaneous - cosmology: theory
General relativity and relativistic cosmology consider space-time as the arena for physics and it is an old question to define space and time. These notions are not covariant and all problems of general relativity and cosmology can be addressed without them, so that they may appear as rather academic (this is equivalent to the choice of a global reference frame). However, on the one hand, the literature refers often to space, for instance when it is affirmed that space is flat (or not), or homogeneous (or not) in a given cosmological model. On the other hand, quantum physics, or its interpretation, requires most often a splitting of space-time into space and time. This points out the necessity of a convenient definition of space in space-time, or equivalently, the choice of a convenient reference frame. The simple example of two inertial observers in Minkowski spacetime, with different velocities, shows that such a definition must be observer-dependent.
An observer needs a frame to do physics in his environment. Although space
is defined locally without ambiguity (by orthogonality to his
worldline, i.e., to his velocity ),
there are many different ways to extend this definition, i.e., to choose a frame
beyond a neighborhood. Since many experiments (e.g., synchronisation procedures)
involve the observer at different moments of his history, a global frame is
constrained to have convenient properties
along his world line O, or at least a part of it (like being
Minkowskian there). But, again, this is far
from being sufficient to determine the choice.
This paper provides a prescription which associates to any observer, defined by his
world line, a unique reference frame with special properties.
A reference frame involves, as a first step, a family of spatial hypersurfaces orthogonal to O, which can be chosen in many different ways. Among popular prescriptions, the Fermi coordinates require the hypersurfaces to be generated by the spacelike geodesics orthogonal to O. But, as it is well known, these spatial surfaces may intersect, even in simple situations like for the Langevin observer (see below). This forbids a definition of time valid far from O (different values of time would be associated with the same event). In cosmology, another popular choice is to select the orthogonal spatial hypersurfaces of homogeneity. But such hypersurfaces do not exist in all space-times, and the choice is clearly not convenient when the observer himself breaks the spatial symmetries (by his acceleration or rotation for instance). The prescription proposed here does not suffer from these drawbacks. In addition, it is the only one to obey the "simultaneity criterion'', absent in all other prescriptions (except in the immediate neighborhood of O): the different points of "space'' are seen as simultaneous (see below for a pecise definition) by the observer. Moreover, it has the additional advantage depending only on the conformal structure of the metric (except for the proper time of the observer), and its validity is broader than those mentioned above (for instance, in the absence of spatial homogeneity).
This prescription has in fact already been applied de facto in some
circumstances, like the Rindler coordinates. But its validity is much
more general, without having too restrictive conditions: for any observer
(inertial or not), in any space-time (with
some conditions, see below), it defines uniquely a "simultaneity
space'' (shortly, space)
at any moment
.
The
do not intersect (even in the situations where the Fermi
hypersurfaces do, like for instance for the Langevin observer, see
below), and they are defined even in the absence of spatial homogeneity.
This allows us to extend the validity of the observer's proper time to
the whole space-time. In the Friedmann-Lemaître models, space so defined does not coincide
with the intuitive idea of what space could be.
Numerous attempts to define a quantization procedure in curved space-time, and/or for non-inertial observers (see, e.g., Birrel & Davis 1982), involve, more or less explicitly, a space-time splitting of space-time. This is especially important for giving a physical interpretation of quantum states in terms of frequencies or particles. For instance, I show below that the current interpretation of the Unruh effect, based on the Rindler coordinates, corresponds in fact to the prescription promoted here.
I emphasize that all quantities introduced in this work are
covariant. This includes all the observer-dependent quantities like
his velocity, acceleration, world-line and the special reference frame
introduced here. An observable quantity (e.g., the energy)
is a combination of a covariant quantity associated with the
observer (e.g., its velocity )
with a
covariant quantity associated with the observed system
(e.g., its momentum-energy tensor). The definition of a global frame
associated with an observer may allow us
to properly define non local quantities related to him.
Since the goal of this work is to construct a reference frame for an observer in a
cosmological situation, one only requires its validity in the part
of space-time which is causally related to him: all events considered
here are causally linked to the observer.
Throughout this paper, by an abuse of langage, I will call "space-time''
the set
of events
inside the particle horizon and the event horizon of the observer, if
they exist. This first restriction
applies to any construction of a global reference frame. Second, the synchronicity
arguments require that null geodesics
admit no conjugate points. This excludes the presence of gravitational
lensing (also incompatible with the other prescriptions).
Since this analysis concerns an observer in a cosmological
situation (convenient for quantization), or for studying the
perturbative development of irregularities, this condition is not
too restrictive (I emphasize again that the validity of this
approach is broader than for concurrent proposals).
In Sect. 2, I will implement the definition of simultaneity space, and the related notions. I show how they allow us to define a global frame convenient to the observer, and a congruence of associated observers. Section 3 applies these results to the inertial and Langevin observers in Minkowski spacetime. Section 4 considers the Rindler observer in Minkowski spacetime, and the associated Unruh effect. Section 5 considers the Friedmann-Lemaître cosmological models.
The most general observer is defined as a timelike world line
parametrized by proper time
.
This defines its velocity
and its
acceleration
everywhere on his world-line.
I call
the unit vector parallel (and in the same
direction) to the acceleration:
![]() |
(1) |
Defining
and
,
the transport is expressed by
![]() |
(2) |
We can naturally associate two different orthonormal frames to the
non-rotating observer, along his world line.
First, there is a parallely-transported frame E but, for a non-inertial observer,
no vector of this frame coincides with the velocity.
Second, there is a Fermi-transported frame f such that
.
Since there is no spatial rotation,
and the law
is verified for
A=0,1,2,3.
For non-rotating observers, the spatial sections (or spaces) keep axial symmetry around the unique spatial direction defined by the acceleration vector. For inertial observers (mainly considered in this paper, except in Sects. 3.1 and 4), the problem is purely 2-dimensional, with spatial spherical symmetry. The general (4-dimensional) case, including the rotating observer, will be examined in a subsequent paper (most of the calculations presented here will remain valid).
A given space-time admits, in general, many time-like foliations
with associated space-like sections, compatible
with the world-line of a
given observer O. I will show that the requirement of
synchronicity allows us to select a unique one, and thus provides a
special global definition of space. This
will require us to consider the whole story of the observer, including his future.
In the following, I will assume that the causal structure of space-time
admits only
light cones without foldings and conjugate points.
These restrictions are however
appropriate for cosmology, and characterize a background space-time convenient for
quantization. This excludes also multi-connected space-times. In the
whole Paper I denote
the one-form metric-dual to a
vector
,
i.e., such that
.
It is well known that it is impossible to define absolute simultaneity in special or general relativity. However, a local prescription of simultaneity or, better, synchronicity, from the point of view of an observer is widely used (see, e.g., Landau & Lifshitz 1966), and defines a local space-time splitting for this observer. The construction of space in this work is based on the extension of this prescription beyond a local neighborhood, with arguments of synchronicity which have a perfectly operational character.
Given an observer O, I define
,
the hypersurface of
synchronicity (HS) of O at proper time
,
as the set of events
related by a null geodesics to both
and
,
where
is an arbitrary interval of proper time for O:
![]() |
(3) |
Given the restrictions above, the surfaces
for different values
of
completely fill
.
This allows to extend
the vector field
to the totality of
by requiring that
it is everywhere unit (
)
and orthogonal to
(Fig. 1). The
vector field
constitutes a foliation of
,
with
the
as transverse (orthogonal) surfaces. Each integral line
of
will be labelled by its intersection
with
(for instance), so
that any point of
can be written
.
Practically,
(evaluated in the spacelike surface
,
see below) can be seen as half the interval of proper time
between the emission of a flash light which illuminates a cosmic object
at x, and the
observation of the resulting image; or, equivalently, as half the interval of
proper time between the
emission of a light ray (or radar signal) by an observer, and its reception after
mirror reflection by the object at x. The requirement
of synchronicity imposes that "the space for
'' is
.
Smarr & York (1978), among others, have considered space-time slicing of space-time associated with a congruence of observers, that they call a kinematics of space-time. The foliation introduced here is of this kind, associated with the congruence of "associated observers''. However, since the latter are defined from the world line of the unique observer O, this procedure defines a unique space-time slicing, from the world line of this unique observer only. In a forthcoming paper, the properties of this "kinematics'' will be discussed in more detail, and compared with other possibilities.
![]() |
Figure 1:
At each point x, the light-rays from the observer (in the past
and in the future) define the vectors
![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Open with DEXTER |
The integral lines of
define a unique family of observers
associated with O, that I will call the canonical observers
associated with O. Care must be taken that they do not necessarily share
the properties of O. For instance, they are not necessarily
geodesic, even when O is, when there is expansion. Along
the word lines generated by
we will call the proper time t,
with
along O.
The properties of space are defined from those of the world-line of
the observer, transported by the past and future light-rays. To
explore them, we define the two null functions
and
such that
the value of
[resp.
]
is the proper time
of the observer O, when it emits a
light-ray reaching x [resp.
,
when it receives a
light-ray emitted from x]. In other words the null hypersurface
[resp.
]
is the future [resp. past] light cone of the observer at proper time
.
We define their (null)
(past and future) generators as
.
Both are
future directed, and normalized so that the frequency emitted or
received by the observer is unity (see below).
It is easy to show that
is defined by the equation
![]() |
(4) |
![]() |
(5) |
Given the normalization
above, we have
![]() |
(6) |
![]() |
(7) |
Everywhere (except on ), we define
![]() |
(8) |
The vector field
is perfectly defined everywhere and characterizes
the family of canonical observers. This family defines a "kinematics'' in the sense of Smarr & York (1978). All the relevant
formalism of projectors, lapse and shift functions (the latter being
zero here, see below), intrinsic
curvature, etc., applies and will be discussed in a forthcoming
paper.
The vector fields
and
are not transported parallely along
the light rays (
is not parallely transported along itself,
in general). To have a clearer view, it is
convenient to introduce the two vector fields
and
which are, by definition, parallely transported along
and
respectively,
,
and which
both coincide with
along the world line of
O (Fig. 2). These requirements are sufficient to define them
everywhere. Both are (time-like) unitary and, when O is inertial,
the spherical symmetry allows to developed them as
![]() |
(9) |
![]() |
(10) |
![]() |
(11) |
![]() |
Figure 2:
The field ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Open with DEXTER |
This example of a bisector frame, in relation to two other frames, may be extended to provide a local surface of synchronicity for two different observers (see Fig. 5 of Ali et al. 1990), useful for the study of the quantum evolution of two interacting particles in space-time (Ali et al. 1990). This will be further developed in a subsequent paper.
There is a closed path starting from the arbitrary point x, going
along the light-ray
to the (inertial) observer, then going back to the
past of the observer along his world-line, and back to the point x
along the light-ray
.
When the observer is inertial,
is parallely transported along his
world-line, so that the transport of
,
then
and then
of
remains parallel. This angular deficit of
,
along
a closed path in the
sheet
(see below) is a mark of the average curvature of space-time
there.
Let us consider a congruence of (non necessarily canonical) objects
with velocity
at the point (event) x in space-time. An object
at x is
seen with redshift
by the observer (in the future)
and sees the observer (in his past) with a redshift
.
For the congruence of canonical observers,
z+=N (x) and
z-=N(x)-1.
These observers are comoving with respect to the coordinate R, i.e.,
they keep a constant value of R.
On the other hand, there is a unique congruence of objects for
which z+=1 [resp. z-=1], those with velocity
[resp.
].
Since we assume that the observer is non-rotating, the problem has a spatial axial symmetry around the direction of his acceleration (and even spherical symmetry if the observer is inertial, i.e., without acceleration).
At each point
(except on O), the two vectors
and
,
or
and
,
or
and
define the same plane Dx in the tangent space
Tx. These
planes generate a foliation with integral surfaces
(Fig. 3). Each
surface
is generated, with time, by a constant spatial direction
from the point of view of the observer. In each
(itself parametrized by
),
we will use R as a spatial (radial) coordinate and T as a temporal
coordinate. Thus any point
.
By definition, a light ray from [to] a point
reaches [resp. starts from] the observer at proper
time T+R [resp. T-R]. The coframe
has for a dual frame
.
These two vectors generate the surface
.
From
![]() |
= | ![]() |
|
![]() |
= | ![]() |
(12) |
![]() |
Figure 3:
At each point
x, ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Open with DEXTER |
The space-like plane Cx orthogonal to all these vectors is
tangent to the past and future light cones at this point, and also to the
hypersurface
at this point. It is the tangent plane to the
surface
![]() |
(13) |
We will choose two orthogonal
unit space-like vectors
and
in C (many choices
are possible; since we only consider non rotating observers, the
problem is essentially two-dimensional and we do not care about the
choice of
and
;
this will be the subject of a forthcoming
paper).
and
form a basis for C, tangent to the 2-surface
.
Any of the previous
pair with these two vectors form a (pseudo-ON or ON) basis of the
tangent space to space-time. Also,
or
,
and
form a pseudo-ON basis for the tangent space to the light
cones.
Since
and
are orthogonal and unitary, the metric can be
written
![]() ![]() |
(14) |
As we have said, T, R (with appropriate angular coordinates) constitute a
well-behaved system of coordinates and provide a global reference
frame in
.
Written in these coordinates the coefficients
of the metric reduce to
.
But N=1 on O and is
stationary (by spherical symmetry arguments) at O if the observer
is inertial. Thus, when the observer is inertial, T and R
are normal
coordinates based on any point of his world line.
We point out that T and R are not, in general, Gaussian normal coordinates since T is not a proper time, except on O (Gaussian normal coordinates cannot, in general, be constructed for this foliation). But they have the advantage that the surfaces of constant "time'' T are global surfaces of simultaneity, although the surfaces of constant Gaussian normal coordinates are not (they verify only local simultaneity).
Now I will consider some special cases.
The inertial observer O has zero acceleration and there is no cosmic
expansion. Its velocity is defined
by
![]() |
(15) |
![]() ![]() |
|||
![]() |
(16) |
![]() |
(17) |
R=![]() |
(18) |
![]() |
Figure 4:
For the inertial observer in Minkowski spacetime,
with arbitrary velocity (rapidity ![]() ![]() ![]() |
Open with DEXTER |
The surface
is the plane of equation
,
inclined by
with respect to the
vertical, and thus orthogonal to the world line of the inertial
observer. Thus, space is different for all inertial observers.
Finally,
and
It is well known that the solution of the celebrated "Langevin's twin
paradox'' lies in geometry. I define a Langevin observer as an
inertial observer which is initially inertial, then suffers an
instantaneous acceleration, and then is inertial again (Fig. 5). Such an
observer is able to meet his twin, who remained always inertial,
with a different lapse of proper time. Is is often quoted (see, e.g.,
Misner et al. 1973)
that it is
impossible to define space globally for such an observer. Here I
show that the synchronicity prescription applies perfectly and
provides an unambiguous definition of space for this observer.
Thus I define the space-time trajectory of this observer as
![]() |
Figure 5: World's line and (cuts of) space at various moments for the Langevin observer. Its line cone is indicated by the dashed lines. |
Open with DEXTER |
The light cone of the observer at t=0,
,
divides the space-time into three
parts I, II and III (see Fig. 5) corresponding to the past, future
and spatially related regions to the acceleration point. Studying the
light-rays from [to] the point x to [from]
the observer gives the functions:
![]() |
(19) |
![]() |
(20) |
![]() |
= | ![]() |
(21) |
![]() |
![]() |
||
= | ![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
R(x) | = | ![]() |
|
= | ![]() |
(22) |
![]() |
= | c x0-s x1 | |
![]() |
(23) |
2T (x) | = | x0+c x0-s x1 | |
![]() |
|||
![]() |
(24) |
2R (x) | = | -x0+c x0-s x1 | |
![]() |
|||
![]() |
(25) |
Let us consider its projection in the (x0,x1) plane (Fig. 5):
![]() |
(26) |
![]() |
(27) |
![]() |
(28) |
![]() |
= | x0+c x0-s x1 | |
![]() |
|||
= | x0+c x0-s x1 +c x1-s x0 - x1, | (29) |
![]() |
(30) |
2R (x) | = | -x0+c x0-s x1 | |
![]() |
|||
= | - x0+c x0-s x1 +c x1-s x0 + x1. | (31) |
This is the simplest example where our prescription differs from the other ones. As it is well known, it is impossible to extend the Fermi coordinates outside the conical regions. And no homogeneous hypersurfaces would be convenient. Thus, in this simple case, our prescription is the only one providing a reference frame associated to the observer valid in the whole space-time, to extend the validity of his proper time, and to consider unambiguous synchronicity procedures (a similar conclusion has been reached by Dolby & Gully 2001).
The Rindler observer in Minkowski spacetime has constant acceleration a. Its velocity is defined
by
![]() |
(32) |
x0 | := | ![]() |
|
x1 | := | ![]() |
(34) |
The condition (33) becomes
,
or
.
It results that
The hypersurface (line)
has the equation
,
which
implies
,
a straight line through
the origin. The surfaces of constant PT-interval
are
the hyperbolae of equation
,
or
.
The forms
![]() |
(35) |
![]() |
(36) |
The solutions of Eq. (33) are given by
![]() |
= | ![]() |
|
![]() |
(37) |
![]() |
(38) |
![]() |
(39) |
The hypersurface
is the [flat] hyperplane through
the origin of equation
(it has as
projection the line seen in the previous section).
The (spatial) metric on
is given by
![]() |
= | ![]() |
|
= | ![]() |
||
= | ![]() |
(40) |
The surfaces of constant PT-interval
are
given by
,
or
![]() |
|||
= (x1)2-(x0)2 +(x2)2+(x3)2. | (41) |
Turning to cosmology, I consider the Friedmann-Lemaître models, i.e., space-times with spatial
sections of maximal symmetry. There exists a special system
of coordinates in which the metric takes the form
![]() |
(42) |
I will consider only a cosmological inertial
observer (CIO) OI which follows the line .
The
problem thus preserves spherical symmetry. All light-rays considered
will be radial, and
will play no role. His proper time
is defined by
.
The functions
and its inverse f such
that
will play an important role.
Since
,
the CIO has a particle horizon and
is defined
inside it, i.e., by
.
For the CIO,
![]() |
(43) |
![]() |
(45) |
![]() |
(46) |
![]() |
(47) |
![]() |
(48) |
![]() |
(49) |
![]() |
(50) |
Space, i.e., the surface
,
has the equation
![]() |
(51) |
Also, the cosmic expansion imprints a curvature onto space: even when
space-time admits spatial sections of constant curvature (like for
instance flat in the Einstein-de Sitter case), this is not the case for the
space. Space is limited by the horizon
,
or T=R. On the
horizon,
and thus
.
Space
tends to become null (light-like).
The PT-interval to a point of this surface is
![]() |
(52) |
To check this in more detail, I consider the example of Einstein-de Sitter space-time, with
and flat spatial sections.
In this case,
and
f(y)=(y/3)3. Thus,
has the equation (Fig. 6)
![]() |
(53) |
![]() |
Figure 6:
Space (
![]() ![]() |
Open with DEXTER |
![]() |
(54) |
All measurements made by an observer, local or not, refer to his proper
time. Thus, when a CIO considers an event in space-time, the relevant time to measure
durations, or to date the event, is not t or
but T defined
above (I recall that T and t coincide on the world line of
the CIO).
On the other hand, the proper distance is intended to measure the interval
between two objects considered simultaneously, i.e., at a common value
of time. But, again, no observer has access to the conformal time
.
Thus, simultaneity (not absolute, but only
relative to the observer) must be defined not by
but by T as we have
explained. This leads to use the proper time distance (that I call
differently to avoid confusion) between two objects, calculated by
integration of the metric element, not along a spatial
section
(or
), but along
,
i.e.,
![]() |
(55) |
Thus, for the CIO, T and R appear as convenient coordinates to measure space and time.
The case of the de Sitter space-time is particularly interesting since, because of its maximal symmetry it has been widely considered as a frame for quantization. As it is well known, it admits different slicings, with spatial sections of constant curvature with positive, zero or negative signs. To each slicing corresponds a convenient system of coordinates. Here I chose the slicing where spatial sections have constant positive curvature since it covers the whole space-time (de Sitter hyperboloid).
The metric is written as
![]() ![]() |
(56) |
The chosen CIO has proper time
so that
.
Thus,
![]() |
(57) |
![]() |
(58) |
![]() |
(59) |
![]() |
(60) |
![]() |
(61) |
The prescription based on synchronicity defines space without ambiguity for any given observer, inertial or not, in arbitrary space-time (without multi-crossing of null geodesics), including Minkowski spacetime and the Friedmann-Lemaître models. Space is relative to the observer (it is in general different for an other observer), and well defined at each instant of its world line. This provides a foliation of space-time, valid for this observer, which may be interpreted as a class of canonically associated observers or a "kinematics'' of space-time (Smarr & York 1978). This provides also a natural reference frame, i.e., global space and time coordinates in the whole space-time, which remains Minkowskian along the world line of the observer (thus, time coincides with its proper time there) and which is pertinent for physical measurements. In many cases (in particular for Rindler observers; see all references concerning the Rindler effect, and Sriramkumar & Padmanabhan 1999), the coordinate system introduced here coincides with that used in the literature with no other justification than being "natural'', and thus provides an a posteriori justification. Also, the prescription presented here appplies to a range wider than other reference frames.
Application to Minkowski spacetime confirms that space and time differ for inertial observers with different velocities. It provides an unambiguous and global definition of space and time for the Langevin observer, for which the other prescriptions do not apply. Applied to the Rindler observer (with uniform acceleration), it leads to space and time coordinates which coincide with the usual Rindler coordinates, thus providing a justification of their use. The corresponding interpretation of the Unruh effect involves the observer-dependant character of space and time.
In cosmology, this prescription provides, for the inertial observer in the general Friedmann-Lemaître model, an unambiguous definition of space, which does not coincide with a spatial section of maximal symmetry. Thus, in the Friedmann-Lemaître models, no inertial observer "sees'' a homogeneous space. The lack of homogeneity of space is due to the curvature corresponding to the expansion law. In particular, space is not flat or homogeneous (although the inertial character of the observer preserves its isotropy) in the Einstein-de Sitter model, sometimes called a "flat universe''! I have also calculated space for the inertial observer in de Sitter space-time, which, again, is not a hypersurface of maximal symmetry.
These results do not modify the cosmological formulae when they are expressed in a covariant form and do not involve a definition of space. However they change those interpretations of observational results, which involve a reference to space (like "space is homogeneous flat'' etc.). This modifies also the interpretation of the usual proper distance: it does not appear as the proper spatial interval between two events occurring at the same time, but rather as a mixed interval between two events which are not synchronous for the observer which performs the measurement (they would be synchronous if the observer were using a watch indicating "conformal time'' rather than "proper time''). Thus I introduce a "proper time-distance'', which represents a spatial interval between two events which are synchronous for the observer. It corresponds to the result of a practical measurement that the observer may perform with his watch indicating his proper time. Its value differs, in general, form the usual proper distance.
This prescription for space could have important implications for interpreting quantum effects in curved space-time, and/or from the point of view of non-inertial observers. Its application to the Rindler observer confirms the usual results of the Unruh effect, and allows a clearer comprehension. In other cases, the prescription adopted here differs from most attempts up to now, since the use of spatial sections with maximal symmetry (rather than space as defined here) does not obey the synchronicity requirements. This suggest a new examination of quantum effects in curved space-time, to be discussed in a forthcoming paper. Also, subsequent work will explore in more detail the application of this procedure to observers with arbitrary acceleration and rotation.